1. The Teleofunctional Account: An
Outline
By `teleosemantics' is meant a
teleofunctional account of what determines the semantic content of mental
representations.1 And any teleofunctional account will employ,
as a pivotal concept, what Millikan calls proper function. The
proper function of some mechanism, trait, or process is what it is
supposed to do, what it has been designed to do, what it
ought to do. More precisely, consider the following simplified
version of Millikan's already simplified version of her definition of
proper function given in Language, Thought and Other Biological
Categories.2
An item X has proper function F only if (i) X is a
reproduction of some prior item that, because of the possession of
certain reproduced properties, actually performed F in the past, and X
exists because of this performance; or (ii) X is the product of a device
that had the performance of F as a proper function and normally performs
F by way of producing an item like X.
This definition, simplified though it is, takes some
unpacking. Firstly, the concept of a proper function is a normative
concept. The proper function of an item is defined in terms of what an
item should do, not what it normally does or is disposed to do. The
concept of proper function, being normative, cannot be defined in causal
or dispositional terms. What something does, or is disposed to do, is not
always what it is supposed to do. This is for three reasons. Firstly, any
mechanism, trait, or process will do many things, not all of which are
part of its proper function. A heart pumps blood; it also makes a thumping
noise and produces wiggly lines on an electrocardiogram. But only the
first of these is its proper function since only pumping blood is
something performed by hearts in the past that explains the existence of
hearts in the present. Secondly, a mechanism, trait, or process can have a
proper function even if it never, or hardly ever, performs it. To use a
flagship example of Millikan's, the proper function of the tail of a sperm
cell is to propel the cell to the ovum. The vast majority of sperm cell
tails, however, do not accomplish this task. Third, a mechanism, trait, or
process may have a proper function and yet not be able to perform it
properly. A person's heart may be malformed and, thus, not be able to pump
blood properly. Nevertheless, pumping blood is its proper function because
ancestors of the person whose heart it is had hearts which pumped blood
and this (in part) explains why they survived and proliferated and, thus,
why the person in question possesses a heart (although not why that heart
is malformed). The concept of proper function is, thus, a normative
concept. The proper function of an item is its Normal function
where, following Millikan, the capitalized `N' indicates that this is a
normative sense of normal and not a causal or dispositional sense.
What underlies the normativity of the concept of proper
function is that the concept is essentially historical in
character. The proper function of an item is determined not by the present
characteristics or dispositions of that item but by its history. In
particular, the possession of a proper function F by an item depends on
that item existing because it possesses certain characteristics that have
been selected for because of the role they play in performing F. This is
the import of (i). That (i) be satisfied is a necessary condition of an
item possessing what Millikan calls a direct proper function. Such
possession is essentially a matter of history. There are no
first-generation direct proper functions.
There is, however, an important distinction to be
observed between direct and derived proper functions. The idea of a
derived proper function is captured by condition (ii). Consider the
distinction between the particular pattern of pigmentation distributed
over the skin of a chameleon and the mechanism that produces this
distribution. Only the mechanism itself possesses a direct proper
function, roughly the function of distributing pigmentation in such a way
that the chameleon will match its immediate environment. However, the
state of the chameleon's skin - the particular distribution of
pigmentation - also possesses a proper function; a function that derives
from the mechanism that produces it. The derived proper function of the
`Pollockian' arrangement of pigmentation in the chameleon's skin is to
match the chameleon to the Jackson Pollock No. 4 upon which the poor
chameleon has been placed. And, unlike direct proper functions, there can
be first-generation derived proper functions. The Pollockian arrangement
of the Chameleon's pigment has the (derived) proper function it has even
if no chameleon has ever been placed on a Pollock No. 4 before,
consequently even if no chameleon has ever produced this particular
pattern before.
The proper or Normal function, direct or derived, of many
evolved items is relational in character. Often this is because the
characteristic has evolved to enable the organism to cope with its
environment: to locate food, evade predators, protect itself against heat
and cold, and so on. Thus, proper functions are often defined relative to
some environmental object or feature: the function of the chameleon's skin
is to make the chameleon the same colour as its immediate environment; the
function of the lion's curved claws is to enable it to catch and hold onto
prey; the function of the bee's dance is to indicate the distance and
direction of nectar. In each case, the function of the characteristic is
specified in terms of the relation it bears to an environmental item. And
the reason for this is that the very reason the characteristic in question
exists is that it has evolved to meet certain environmental pressures.
The core idea of the teleofunctional account of
representation is that the mechanisms responsible for mental
representation are evolutionary products also. As such, they will have
(direct) relational proper functions. The idea, then, is that the
representational capacities of a given cognitive mechanism are specified
in terms of the environmental objects or features that are incorporated
into that mechanism's (direct) relational proper function. That is, if a
cognitive mechanism M has evolved in order to detect an environmental
feature E, then this is what makes an appropriate state S of M
about E; this is what makes state S mean that E, this is
what gives the state S the content that E. In this way, the
representational content of a cognitive state S derives from the direct
relational proper function of the mechanism M that produces S, and S
itself has the derived proper function of representing E.
2. Strengths of the Teleofunctional
Account
The teleofunctional account is one way
of attempting to naturalize semantics: very roughly, to show how
the semantic properties of mental representations can arise out of
non-semantic properties. One of the most significant strengths of the
teleofunctional account is its ability to resolve a problem that plagued
other attempts at naturalizing semantics, attempts embodied in both causal
and purely informational accounts of representation. This problem is that
of misrepresentation.
Consider a mental representation of a
horse. Adopting common practice, I shall refer to this by way of the
capitalized HORSE to show that we are talking about the representation and
not the horse itself. The representation HORSE, it seems, means `horse'.
This is what makes it the representation it is, and not the representation
of something else. However, it also seems possible, indeed likely, that
the representation HORSE can be caused by things that are not horses.
Donkeys in the distance and cows on a dark night might, in certain
circumstances, be equally efficacious in causing a tokening of the HORSE
representation. Now, according to an informational account, representation
is to be explained in terms of nomic dependence. However, if the
representation HORSE can be tokened in the absence of horses, then HORSE
does not seem nomically dependent on horses in the relevant sense. Rather,
what HORSE does seem nomically dependent upon is not the property of being
a horse but the disjunctive property of being a horse or a
donkey-in-the-distance or a cow-on-a-dark-night. Thus, if information is a
matter of nomic dependence, and if representation is a matter of
information, then we seem forced to say that what HORSE represents is not
the property of being a horse but the above disjunctive property. But,
fairly clearly, when we think, for example, that Arkle was a horse, and
thus token the representation HORSE, we do not think that Arkle was either
a horse or a donkey-in-the- distance or a cow-on-a-dark-night. We think
that Arkle was a horse. And if I am inclined to have a flutter on the 2.45
at Uttoxeter, still less do I think of myself as betting on something that
is either a horse or a donkey-in-the-distance or a cow-on-a-dark-night.
The moral of the story is that there seems to be a divergence between the
meaning of a representation and the information carried by that
representation. The information is disjunctive in a way that the meaning
is not. This problem of misrepresentation is, thus, often referred to as
the disjunction problem.
One strength of the teleofunctional
account is that it yields an elegant solution to the problem of
misrepresentation. HORSE represents the property of being a horse and not
the above disjunctive property because the direct proper function of the
mechanism that produces HORSE is to produce this representation in the
presence of horses and not donkeys or cows. That is, the HORSE
representation, we can suppose, is a state of a mechanism M. And this
mechanism has the direct proper function of producing HORSE in the
presence of HORSES. That is what (presumably among other things) the
mechanism has been selected for. It does not have the proper function of
producing HORSE in the presence of donkeys or cows, whether in the
distance or on a dark night. And, on a teleofunctional account, the
content of a state S of mechanism M derives from the direct proper
function of M. Thus HORSE is about horses and not about donkeys, cows, or
disjunctions of the three. Providing a solution to the disjunction problem
requires, in effect, detaching the content of a representation from the
property with which it is maximally correlated. And this is precisely what
the teleofunctional account allows us to do. Representation, on this view,
derives from proper function. And proper function, being normative, cannot
be defined in causal or dispositional terms. The fact that HORSE is
tokened not only in the presence of horses but also in that of donkeys and
cows, and is maximally correlated with a disjunction of the three, is,
therefore, irrelevant. What determines the representational content of
HORSE is not what environmental item in fact does causally produce it, but
what should causally produce it. And this is determined by the
direct proper function of its producing mechanism.
3. Unresolved Problems?
The problem that has perhaps most
exercised both opponents and proponents of teleofunctional accounts is
often referred to as the problem of indeterminacy. Some have argued
that a teleofunctional account of representation entails the indeterminacy
of mental content. It does so because, it is claimed, the biological
function of a mechanism, trait, or process is itself indeterminate.
Consider an example that by now has
assumed the status of a classic. Frogs catch flies by way of a rapid
strike with their tongue. Thus, it is plausible to suppose, mediating
between the environmental presence of a fly and the motor response of a
tongue strike is some sort of neural mechanism that registers the fly's
presence in the vicinity and causes the strike of the frog's tongue. In
more detail, we might suppose the presence of the fly causes the relevant
mechanism to go into state S, and its being in state S causes, by way of
various motor intermediaries, the tongue to strike. According to the
teleofunctional account, the content of state S should be, roughly,
`fly!', or `fly, there!', and it derives this content from the fact that
the proper or Normal function of its underlying mechanism is to detect the
presence of flies. The state is, thus about flies; it means
that there are flies in the vicinity.
There is, however, an alternative
construal of the function of the mechanism. On this construal, what the
mechanism in question has been selected to respond to are little ambient
black things (To avoid becoming entangled in a completely different issue,
let me make it clear that the little ambient black things are
environmental entities and not dots on a retinal image). The proper
function of the mechanism, on this construal, is to mediate between little
ambient black things and tokenings of a state that causes the frog's
tongue to strike. This state will then beabout little ambient black
things and will, therefore, mean that there are little ambient
black things in the vicinity.
The proper function of the mechanism is
different in each case since, in the latter case but not the former, the
frog's mechanism is functioning properly or Normally when the frog strikes
at a little ambient black thing that is not, in fact, a fly (but, say, a
lead pellet or `BB'). And the content underwritten by the function is
different in each case since not all little ambient black things are
flies.
The problem of indeterminacy, it is
argued, arises because there seems to be no fact of the matter that could
determine which of these interpretations is the correct one. Evolutionary
theory, it has been argued, does not provide any means of adjudicating
between these interpretations. That is, evolutionary theory, by itself, is
neutral between the claim that the neural mechanism Normally mediates fly
strikes and the claim that the mechanism Normally mediates little ambient
black thing strikes that are situated in an environment where little
ambient black things are Normally flies. Therefore, whether the mechanism
is about, and hence means, that there are flies in the vicinity or that
there are little ambient black things in the vicinity is also
indeterminate. In this way, the teleofunctional account of representation
is thought to entail the indeterminacy of mental content. And so, to use
Fodor's colourful expression, it is most unlikely that Darwin is going to
pull Brentano's chestnuts out of the fire.3
The most influential recent attempts to
resolve the problem of indeterminacy can be divided into two sorts,
according to whether they endorse what are sometimes known as a
stimulus-based or a benefit-based account of representation.
In his more recent writings. Dretske endorses a stimulus based account of
representation.4 According to Dretske, when an indicator C
indicates both F and G, and its indication of G is via its indication of
F, then C acquires the function of indicating F. And this is so even if it
is G that is most relevant to explaining the indicational role of C. Thus,
to use an example made famous by Dretske himself, the magnetosome
possessed by certain marine bacteria represents the direction of
geomagnetic north and not the direction of oxygen-free water. It
represents this even though the purpose of the magnetosome - the reason
for which the magnetosome has been selected - is to direct the bacteria
away from the oxygen-rich surface water that would be lethal for it. Thus,
the magnetosome represents geomagnetic north and not the direction of
oxygen free water even though the only relevance - or benefit - of
geomagnetic north to the bacterium is that by heading for geomagnetic
north it thereby moves into oxygen-free water (in the southern hemisphere
the magnetosomes are reversed). Geomagnetic north is the stimulus for the
magnetosome, and representation, for Dretske, follows or tracks stimulus
not benefit.
Millikan, on the other hand, endorses a
benefit-based account of representation. To this end, she has, in her more
recent writings, been emphasizing the role played by the consumers,
rather than the producers, of representations in fixing content
(and this puts her position somewhat at odds with the outline of the
teleofunctional account given in the opening section).5 In her
later works, Millikan argues that while the mechanism that produces a
representation may determine that representation's status as a
representation, it is the consumer of the representation, the mechanism
(typically) that interprets and uses the representation that determines
its content. Thus, in the case of Dretske's marine bacteria, what the
magnetosome represents, for Millikan, is only what its consumers require
that it correspond to in order to fulfil their functions. And what these
mechanisms require, MIllikan argues, is only that the pull on the
magnetosome be in the direction of oxygen-free water. Thus, the
magnetosome represents the direction of oxygen-free water, not the
direction of geomagnetic north.
I think it is fair to say that both
stimulus- and benefit-based approaches face unresolved difficulties.
However, perhaps most fundamentally, it is simply unclear what could force
the issue one way or another. While defences of each position are often
ingenious, it is difficult to see what argument could rationally compel on
to adopt one approach over the other. In a recent paper, I have argued, in
effect, that there may, in fact, be no need to adjudicate between
approaches.6 This is because acceptance of both a
stimulus- and a benefit-based approach does not, in fact, lead to the
indeterminacy of mental content. Central to my account is the idea that
possession, by a single mechanism, of two non-equivalent proper functions
does not lead to indeterminacy of content as long as the content
underwritten by each function does not attach to the same thing. And the
possession by a single mechanism of two distinct proper functions does not
entail that the contents underwritten by each function both attach to the
mechanism. I distinguish between what I call organismic and
algorithmic proper functions of a mechanism. In the case of the
frog, the algorithmic proper function of the mechanism might be to detect
the presence of little ambient black things, while the organismic proper
function is to enable the organism - the frog - to detect the presence of
(following Gibson) an affordance of the environment: eatability.
(On this account, detection of flies is not a proper function of the
mechanism but a consequence of the mechanism performing its proper
function in Normal conditions). The algorithmic proper function
underwrites attribution of the content `Little ambient black thing,
there!' to the mechanism (or to a state of the mechanism). But the
organismic proper function, since its function is not to detect eatability
as such but, rather, to enable the organism to detect the presence
of eatability, underwrites attribution of the content `Eatability, there!'
not to the mechanism but to the organism. Thus, since the content in each
case attaches to different objects, we do not have a genuine case of
indeterminacy but, rather, a case of two perfectly determinate contents
being attributed to distinct things.
Notes.
1. This definition is taken from
Millikan, `Compare and contrast Dretske, Fodor, and Millikan on
teleosemantics' in her White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for
Alice, Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 123.
2. Millikan's original definition of the
notion of proper function is, in reality, a series of definitions, spread
out over the opening chapter of Language, Thought, and Other Biological
CategoriesPhilosophy of
Science, 56, 2, 1989, 288-302. Reprinted in White Queen
Psychology, 13-29.
3. Jerry Fodor, `A Theory of Content I'
in A Theory of Content and Other Essay, Cambridge, Mass., MIT
Press, (1990), 70.
4. Fred Dretske, `Reply to reviewers',
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 1, 4, 1990, 819-39.
5. See, for example, Millikan, `Compare,
and contrast Dretske, Fodor, and Millikan on teleosemantics'.
6. Mark Rowlands, `Teleological
Semantics', in Mind, Vol. 106, no. 422, April 1997, 279-303.
Top
of
page
|